Print
REVISED
|

Environmental aesthetics

DOI
10.4324/9780415249126-M047-2
Versions
Published
2011
DOI: 10.4324/9780415249126-M047-2
Version: v2,  Published online: 2011
Retrieved April 19, 2024, from https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/environmental-aesthetics/v-2

5. Positions and problems: noncognitive approaches

The questions of what and how to appreciate aesthetically in the world at large have generated a number of different philosophical positions within environmental aesthetics (Kemal and Gaskell 1993, Sepänmaa 1997, Berleant and Carlson 1998, Berleant 2002), but two basic kinds of approaches can be distinguished. The first takes as its starting point environments, in many cases large-scale natural environments, that most literally and completely surround appreciators, impinging on all their senses and absorbing them as integral parts of the environments themselves. The most well-known of this kind of approach, the aesthetics of engagement, considers this kind of engaged experience of environments to be the essence of aesthetic appreciation. It holds that appreciators must transcend traditional dichotomies, such as subject/object, and diminish the distance between themselves and objects of appreciation, aiming at total, multisensory immersion of the former within the latter. This engagement approach to the aesthetic appreciation of environments is, moreover, not restricted to large natural environments, but is advocated as a model for the appreciation of all kinds of environments and objects, including even some works of art (Berleant 1992). Thus it is a major factor in broadening the scope of environmental aesthetics beyond that of both landscape aesthetics and traditional philosophical aesthetics and thereby shaping it into a field not simply focusing on nature or art, but encompassing the aesthetic appreciation of the world at large.

The engagement approach centres on immediate sensory involvement with any object of aesthetic appreciation. Related approaches emphasize similar dimensions of the appreciation of both natural and human environments, arguing that these dimensions, although perhaps not exhaustive of aesthetic appreciation, are nonetheless essential to it. Different positions stress various kinds of emotional and feeling-related states and responses, for example, arousal, affection, reverence, intimacy, wonder and ineffability (e.g. Carroll, in Kemal and Gaskell 1993). The engagement approach and these related positions thus emphasize what might be considered the more noncognitive dimensions of aesthetic experience. Consequently, they tend to imply rather subjective answers to the questions of what and how to appreciate aesthetically in environments. They suggest that, since appreciators appear to lack resources such as frames, artists, traditions and designs, as well as the guidance these provide, questions concerning the appreciation of everyday environments cannot be concretely and definitively answered. The implication is that for the world at large there is perhaps no such thing as correct or appropriate aesthetic appreciation; rather, it is more a matter of appreciators opening themselves to being immersed, responding as they will, and enjoying what they can.

In granting a central place to immediate sensory and feeling responses to environments, the engagement and related positions draw attention to important components of aesthetic experience. These views also have other strengths: they effectively treat the central issue of the field by clearly recognizing the open, unlimited and promiscuous nature of the objects of appreciation of environmental aesthetics and by correctly construing these features as aesthetic virtues rather than as defects of such objects. Moreover, they require no complex or elaborate theory to account for the aesthetic appreciation of environments and thus have an immediate intuitive appeal. Nonetheless, such approaches also have problems. For example, perhaps they too quickly embrace an overly subjective account of the aesthetic appreciation of the world at large. In doing so, they appear to leave little room for the distinction between more and less appropriate aesthetic appreciation. Consequently, they seemingly not only endorse a somewhat trivial or superficial rather than a serious or deep form of aesthetic experience of the world at large, but also create a worrisome rift between the nature of such experience and the aesthetic experience of art, which clearly allows both for more or less appropriate aesthetic appreciation and for serious, deep as well as trivial, superficial forms of it.

Print
Citing this article:
Carlson, Allen. Positions and problems: noncognitive approaches. Environmental aesthetics, 2011, doi:10.4324/9780415249126-M047-2. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Taylor and Francis, https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/environmental-aesthetics/v-2/sections/positions-and-problems-noncognitive-approaches.
Copyright © 1998-2024 Routledge.

Related Articles