Access to the full content is only available to members of institutions that have purchased access. If you belong to such an institution, please log in or find out more about how to order.


Print

Contents

Non-monotonic logic

DOI
10.4324/9780415249126-Y079-1
DOI: 10.4324/9780415249126-Y079-1
Version: v1,  Published online: 1998
Retrieved May 03, 2024, from https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/non-monotonic-logic/v-1

Article Summary

A relation of inference is ‘monotonic’ if the addition of premises does not undermine previously reached conclusions; otherwise the relation is non-monotonic. Deductive inference, at least according to the canons of classical logic, is monotonic: if a conclusion is reached on the basis of a certain set of premises, then that conclusion still holds if more premises are added.

By contrast, everyday reasoning is mostly non-monotonic because it involves risk: we jump to conclusions from deductively insufficient premises. We know when it is worthwhile or even necessary (for example, in medical diagnosis) to take the risk. Yet we are also aware that such inference is ‘defeasible’ – that new information may undermine old conclusions. Various kinds of defeasible but remarkably successful inference have traditionally captured the attention of philosophers (theories of induction, Peirce’s theory of abduction, inference to the best explanation, and so on). More recently logicians have begun to approach the phenomenon from a formal point of view. The result is a large body of theories at the interface of philosophy, logic and artificial intelligence.

Print
Citing this article:
Fuhrmann, Andre. Non-monotonic logic, 1998, doi:10.4324/9780415249126-Y079-1. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Taylor and Francis, https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/non-monotonic-logic/v-1.
Copyright © 1998-2024 Routledge.

Related Searches

Topics