Access to the full content is only available to members of institutions that have purchased access. If you belong to such an institution, please log in or find out more about how to order.


Print
REVISED
|

Content, non-conceptual

DOI
10.4324/9780415249126-N076-2
Versions
Published
2011
DOI: 10.4324/9780415249126-N076-2
Version: v2,  Published online: 2011
Retrieved April 19, 2024, from https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/content-non-conceptual/v-2

Article Summary

A mental state has intentional content when it represents features of the world. The intentional content of a belief can be characterized in terms of concepts: the content of the belief that fish swim is characterized by the concept of fish and the concept of swimming. The contents of beliefs are, for this reason, often described as conceptual. One way to explain this idea is to say that to have a belief, one has to possess the concepts which characterize the belief’s content. Another way to explain it is to say that the propositional content of the belief is made up of concepts. Some philosophers believe that certain mental states have non conceptual contents: either in the sense that these states represent the world without the subject having to possess the relevant concepts, or in the sense that their propositional contents are not made up of concepts. The main examples of these putative mental states with nonconceptual contents are conscious perceptual experiences and the nonconscious states of cognitive information-processing systems (such as the visual system).

Print
Citing this article:
Crane, Tim. Content, non-conceptual, 2011, doi:10.4324/9780415249126-N076-2. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Taylor and Francis, https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/content-non-conceptual/v-2.
Copyright © 1998-2024 Routledge.

Related Searches

Topics

Related Articles